The ethics of privacy

Privacy is a fundamental human right recognized in the UN Declaration of Human Rights, the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and in many other international and regional treaties. Privacy underpins human dignity and other key values such as freedom of association and freedom of speech. It has become one of the most important human rights issues of the modern age. And yet, for many, the GDPR is the beginning of privacy law as we know it. The most remarkable difference being the introduction of some really sizeable fines.   So how does this affect the ethics of privacy?

Privacy is, in its nature, an element of compliance. Compliance with privacy laws and with the “intention” of privacy laws is how we show optimal data protection.  When talking of compliance, I always say that “Compliance is not about just doing the right thing, but showing we are doing the right thing”. Compliance is only possible with accountability. No one ever challenges the concept that compliance is about doing the right thing. We should remodel our approach to privacy away from compliance with law, but towards the behaviour of doing the right thing. The GDPR helps us to show we are doing the right thing; it helps us to show our accountability, but it is not the reason privacy exists.

Why is this important for companies? Privacy is now a central element of business ethics.  It forms part of the corporate approach to mitigating controversial subjects in order to gain public trust and support. No matter what industry, data is essential to the functioning of business. Without an ethical approach to treating data, it will not be entrusted to those who need it most to make business turn and of course, maintain reputation, help avoid significant financial and legal issues, and thus, ultimately benefit everyone involved.

A “purpose”​ element: what is inside the controller’s mind?

In ‘Opinion 4/2007’ on the concept of personal data, Working Party 29 (‘WP29’) identified four building blocks in the definition of personal data – ‘any information’, ‘relating to’, identified or identifiable’, ‘natural person’. They remained the same in the GDPR, thus rendering ‘Opinion 4/2007’ relevant for understanding the concept of personal data. 

However, WP29, instead of eliminating all subjectivity to the extent possible, seemed to add some unclarity to the explanation of what ‘relating to’ means.

WP29 sets out that ‘in order to consider that the data “relate” to an individual, a “content” element OR a “purpose” element OR a “result” element should be present’. In turn, ‘“purpose” element can be considered to exist when the data are used or are likely to be used, taking into account all the circumstances surrounding the precise case, with the purpose to evaluate, treat in a certain way or influence the status or behaviour of an individual’.

By itself, an idea to decide on whether the data are personal or not through the interpretation of the “purpose” element is quite controversial due to the subjective (rather than objective) nature of the notion of purpose.

An example given by WP29 brings this problem front and center:

Passenger vehicles owned by a transportation company suffer repeated damage when they are dirtied with graffiti. In order to evaluate the damage and to facilitate the exercise of legal claims against their authors, the company organises a register containing information about the circumstances of the damage, as well as images of the damaged items and of the “tags” or “signature” of the author. At the moment of entering the information into the register, the authors of the damage are not known nor to whom the “signature” corresponds. It may well happen that it will never be known. However, the purpose of the processing is precisely to identify individuals to whom the information relates as the authors of the damage, so as to be able to exercise legal claims against them. Such processing makes sense if the data controller expects as “reasonably likely” that there will one day be means to identify the individual. The information contained in the pictures should be considered as relating to “identifiable” individuals, the information in the register as “personal data”, and the processing should be subject to the data protection rules, which allow such processing as legitimate under certain circumstances and subject to certain safeguards.

Most likely, it is only common sense that can lead to the conclusion that the purpose is to precisely identify authors of the graffiti. However, the controller can potentially argue that it keeps the register and images for some other internal purposes not connected with the purpose of future identification. As a result, we may end up being engaged in a discussion about true intentions of the controller which might not be established easily due to a lack of the factual grounds.

The issue described above may prima facie seem to be solely theoretical. Moreover, the language used by the GDPR contains various ‘floating’ criteria implying the necessity to conduct evaluations on a case-by-case basis. However, one should not overlook that, by applying the concept of purpose as described above, we decide on whether the data are personal or not, and a positive answer inevitably triggers set of responsibilities vested in the controller under the GDPR and Member States laws. It can be assumed that more certainty is need when addressing such a fundamental issue which may (or may not) trigger application of the data protection legislation in general.

Interestingly, the GDPR suffers from the same flaw like the WP29 ‘Opinion 4/2007’. Under Article 9(1), processing of biometric data for the purpose of uniquely identifying a natural person is prohibited (unless one of the exemptions under Article 9(2) applies). This brings us back to the issue of identification of the controller’s intention. Ironically enough, Recital 51 applies more objective criteria when addressing the same issue:

“The processing of photographs should not systematically be considered to be processing of special categories of personal data as they are covered by the definition of biometric data only when processed through a specific technical means allowing the unique identification or authentication of a natural person

In other words, under Recital 51, it is ability of technical means to identify individuals that plays a key role (and not just purposes pursued by the controller). Unfortunately, this wording has been changed in Article 9(1) requiring to identify the subjective purposes (instead of objective abilities).

Ratsit is so kind as to remove sensitve data from public eyes

I am being continually amazed by the lack of respect there is here in Sweden for personal data. I have written so much on this subject already. However I came across this article a couple of weeks ago concerning Ratsit (who are one of those companies that have an ‘utgivningsbevis’ which means they can use our personal data and make it public to make money). Well they have been so kind as to remove from their search results names of vulnerable women living in shelters, and other categories of individuals that should be protected!

Thank you for being so considerate Ratsit…… now would you be so kind as to remove my name too…..